Skip to main content

POINT OF VIEW

Transpl Int, 21 March 2022
This article is part of the Special Issue Ethical issues in organ donation and transplantation View all 17 articles

Donor Autonomy and Self-Sacrifice in Living Organ Donation: An Ethical Legal and Psychological Aspects of Transplantation (ELPAT) View

Nizam Mamode
Nizam Mamode1*Kristof Van AsscheKristof Van Assche2Lisa BurnappLisa Burnapp1Aisling CourtneyAisling Courtney3David van DellenDavid van Dellen4Mireille HouthoffMireille Houthoff5Hannah MapleHannah Maple1Greg MoorlockGreg Moorlock6Frank J. M. F. Dor,Frank J. M. F. Dor7,8Annette Lennerling,Annette Lennerling9,10
  • 1Department of Transplantation, Guys and St Thomas NHS Foundation Trust, London, United Kingdom
  • 2Research Group Personal Rights and Property Rights, University of Antwerp, Antwerp, Belgium
  • 3Regional Nephrology and Transplant Unit, Belfast City Hospital, Belfast, United Kingdom
  • 4Department of Renal and Pancreas Transplantation, Manchester University NHS Foundation Trust, Manchester, United Kingdom
  • 5Erasmus MC Transplant Institute, Department of Internal Medicine, University Medical Centre, Erasmus University Rotterdam, Rotterdam, Netherlands
  • 6Warwick Medical School, University of Warwick, Coventry, United Kingdom
  • 7Imperial College Renal and Transplant Centre, Hammersmith Hospital, Imperial College Healthcare NHS Trust, London, United Kingdom
  • 8Department of Surgery and Cancer, Imperial College, London, United Kingdom
  • 9The Transplant Centre, Sahlgrenska University Hospital, Gothenburg, Sweden
  • 10Institute of Health and Care Sciences, The Sahlgrenska Academy, University of Gothenburg, Gothenburg, Sweden

Clinical teams understandably wish to minimise risks to living kidney donors undergoing surgery, but are often faced with uncertainty about the extent of risk, or donors who wish to proceed despite those risks. Here we explore how these difficult decisions may be approached and consider the conflicts between autonomy and paternalism, the place of self-sacrifice and consideration of risks and benefits. Donor autonomy should be considered as in the context of the depth and strength of feeling, understanding risk and competing influences. Discussion of risks could be improved by using absolute risk, supra-regional MDMs and including the risks to the clinical team as well as the donor. The psychological effects on the donor of poor outcomes for the untransplanted recipient should also be taken into account. There is a lack of detailed data on the risks to the donor who has significant co-morbidities.

Introduction

The donation of a solid organ for transplantation by a person who is alive at the time represents a unique event in healthcare, since the donor will gain no physical benefit from undergoing major surgery, which has a low but nevertheless significant rate of major complications and death (1, 2). Living donors are usually highly motivated individuals, whose appetite for risk differs substantially from that of the healthcare team (3). This may lead to conflicts between the clinical team and potential donors-some examples are given in Figure 1. Were the decisions of the clinical teams correct? This article explores the issues raised by these cases and others, and considers the principles which might help to guide decision-making. It is an overview aimed at healthcare professionals, and is not intended to be an in-depth ethical review. Suggestions for further reading are given in Figure 2.

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

FIGURE 1. Examples of potentially difficult decisions regarding living donor candidates.

FIGURE 2
www.frontiersin.org

FIGURE 2. Suggested further reading.

Autonomy Versus Paternalism

Although not universally adopted, principlism remains the dominant approach to medical ethics (4), particularly amongst the clinically-orientated. Under a principlist approach, four principles are considered in the determination of whether an intervention is ethically appropriate: autonomy, beneficence, non-maleficence, justice (5). Beauchamp and Childress suggest that each principle should be afforded equal weight, but nonetheless autonomy is often regarded as “first amongst equals” (6). In living kidney donation, beneficence is difficult to both specify and quantify accurately. There is likely to be some psychological benefit (7, 8) but there is clearly no physical benefit of donation itself. Whilst non-maleficence, or more specifically the minimisation of harm is a concomitant aim of donation surgery, some harm is unavoidable, such as the physical harm routinely associated with surgery, and sometimes unanticipated complications occur. Although teams attempt to assess the risk to the donor independently, the benefit to the recipient also plays a part (9), since without this the donation would not be justified (Figure 3). Some have argued for a “donor-centred” approach, where the importance of the emotional benefits to the donor is expanded when considering risks (10).

FIGURE 3
www.frontiersin.org

FIGURE 3. The interplay of potentially conflicting ethical principles.

The clinical team are also agents here and ultimately responsible for decisions to offer donation as an option to an individual: an on-table death of a donor would certainly affect them profoundly, and potentially their programme and others, and hence other patients. But this could perhaps be overcome by having centralisation of high risk cases in dedicated centres or by having surgeons for “high risk” cases in centres, where everyone understood that the risks were higher and appropriate protections were in place, including transparent audit, support for staff, and avoidance of punitive actions in the event of below average outcomes.

It is quite common for clinical teams to adopt a degree of paternalism (11), whereby autonomy is infringed upon to some extent in order to serve a patient’s best interests. Consider, for example, the postoperative patient who would rather not get out of bed, but is essentially cajoled into doing so. In this scenario, it might be considered that the patient’s wish to stay in bed is not strongly held, and that it is heavily in their best interests to mobilise, so beneficence overrules respecting the rather weak autonomous wishes of the patient. It might then seem logical that there is a gradation of potential benefits or harms, which could be weighed against a scale of autonomous desires of increasing strength, rather than simple binary outputs for these potentially competing interests. Considering that there may be effectively different levels of autonomy, related to a degree of understanding and strength of feeling, may help here. Similarly, it might be considered that there is a scale of paternalism, ranging from “weak to strong (12)” or “soft to hard (13).” In practical terms, such an interpretation is necessarily a matter of subjective judgement, but a potentially paternalistic approach might include consideration of the following: how strongly do you feel about donating, and why? Do you have a reasonable understanding of the risks? How likely are you to regret this later? Despite the difficulty in answering these questions, it might be a first step in resolving the conflicts described above.

A key problem in considering the importance of autonomy in medical decision making is the difficulty in the determination of the value that should be accorded to a particular autonomous wish. That is, at what point does an apparently autonomous decision carry sufficient weight to outweigh other considerations (9). This is a key issue when considering decision making in children, who may not yet be considered independent and adults who are incompetent to make any decision, but whose wishes are nevertheless taken into account. Indeed, children not infrequently express a wish to donate to siblings, but in most jurisdictions this would be refused (14, 15). Perhaps a useful ethical approach would be to balance the clinical team’s view of the potential benefits and harms, with the depth and strength of conviction of the individual concerned. One might consider a central aspect of autonomy to be the ability to use relevant information to reason in certain ways and adopt a considered approach (5). Thus, it might be, for example, that an experienced transplant surgeon with non-insulin dependent diabetes who felt strongly that they wished to donate to their spouse could have a reasonable understanding of the risks, and should be allowed to proceed. In clinical practice, a clear understanding of the risks is often given greater validity in terms of decision making; however, it could be argued that neither depth nor strength of conviction are valid reasons for assessing the degree of autonomy. Furthermore, freedom from external pressures beyond the clinical team, for example from family members, is an important consideration in determination of the extent to which a patient’s wishes are truly autonomous.

Risk Benefit Balance

The risks of donor nephrectomy are mortality 1 in 3,000 and major complications 2–5% (1, 2), while for a living liver donation the mortality rate is 1 in 200 (16). This could mean that a “high risk” kidney donor might still be exposed to less risk than a low risk liver donor. It could be argued that the difference here is the combination of lack of availability of other options and need for urgent surgery in the recipient, since a liver patient might not survive for long without a transplant, while most kidney recipients would have a dialysis option. However, in considering the risk/benefit balance for the donor, the implication must be that the difference is only a psychological one, and not physical-that is, the liver donor has the higher psychological risk of seeing a loved one die, which justifies the higher risk of donation. There can’t be any other moral imperative to expose the donor to higher risks because the stakes are higher for the recipient. The logical extension of this argument suggests, however, that outcomes other than death might have a profound psychological detrimental effect on the potential donor-for example, parental donation to a child who is not thriving on dialysis, or spousal donation where the life of the donor is severely impacted by having an unwell partner (17).

One of the common errors in considering the risks of donation is to focus on relative, rather than absolute, risk. The use of absolute risk has been recommended specifically for living donors (18). A mortality rate of 1 in 1,500 is twice the normal risk but still very low, and lower than for the liver donor. Furthermore, we do not have good data on what the actual risks are in those with co-morbidities, in part because they are usually refused surgery (19). For example, previous myocardial infarction is often an exclusion criterion for kidney donors, yet if successful rehabilitation has taken place, risk factors addressed and cardiac tests are adequate, then it probably does not confer a high absolute risk (20, 21). An alternative approach might be to consider what is an acceptable upper mortality rate, and to permit donation if this threshold is not reached, even if the relative risk is doubled. Clearly challenges would remain in determining this rate, and in assessing individual donors who are below this threshold. There is certainly a need to determine more accurately and objectively the risks to both donor and recipient, in order to make the appropriate decision-just as we may not be aware of the real perioperative risk to a donor conferred by a co-morbidity, data on the risk to the recipient of not proceeding with a living donor transplant at that time is often lacking.

It is also important to consider long term as well as perioperative risk. There is even less data here. For example, the lifetime risk of ESRD after LDN in a 70-year-old man is 0.15% (95% CI 0.05, 0.28), and the relative risk for ESRD from non-insulin dependent diabetes is 3.01 (1.91, 4.74)- the absolute risk would appear to be low, but we have no data on the effect of donation on subsequent ESRD in this scenario (22).

Risk aversion may sometimes vary with specialty; surgeons and nephrologists sometimes have differing appetites for risk. Whilst the multidisciplinary meeting (MDM) or protocols and guidelines may mitigate some of these differences, an exploration of how these operate in practice, and the underlying thought processes could help in smoothing decisions. An emerging literature on cognitive biases and loss aversion, where the fear of a low probability but high loss outcome tends to outweigh potential gains, in decision making indicates an interesting start (23, 24).

Finally, risks apply not only to the potential donor, but to the operating surgeon, the clinical team, and to a national programme, since donor deaths have typically impacted on all of these. One way to mitigate this might be to take national decisions on high-risk cases, in a sense as a supra-regional MDM, which would in part shift some of the risk away for the local team in the same way that local MDM advice shares the risk beyond the operating surgeon. Equity of access is an important principle to consider, since widely differing views may pertain in different centres (18). It is also important to consider the risk to the recipient-a donor who suffers severe complications may lead to considerable distress for the recipient.

Self-Sacrifice and Heroism

We applaud self-sacrifice in many walks of life-firefighters, military, even sport, such as Formula 1, mountaineering, round the world sailing. Those who take risks to save others, or for glory or money, are often considered heroes. Why is someone who takes a risk as a donor different?

It might be argued that the difference is that they need a clinical team to facilitate their operation- but then many of the others listed above need support from teams. Arguably in these cases there is oversight of risk by another group. For example, a military unit might be ordered to retreat if the risk is too high, or the race director may stop a Grand Prix if rain makes it unsafe. It could be considered that the MDM in each unit provides a similar oversight, but given the potential risks to individual clinicians, and to programmes, of poor outcomes as mentioned above it might be that we are not independent enough. The wide variability in assessment criteria illustrates the difficulty here (19, 25). Nevertheless, if the local clinical team is reluctant to proceed, there is an argument for a second opinion, or for national or regional bodies to make these assessments.

Extreme Risks

Some potential donors might have a limited life expectancy, for example Huntington’s chorea, or a reduced capacity due to illness, for example, early dementia, but still wish to donate. In these cases, it might be argued that if the organ is unaffected by the underlying medical condition, donation does not hasten death, and there is sufficient capacity to make the decision, it would be reasonable to proceed (25). However other donors might wish to take more extreme risks-for example, donating their heart and thus ending their life (2628). Similarly, there are those who are undergoing euthanasia (28), and wish to donate as part of that process, as detailed in Figure 4. In this case, the acceptance of such a donor would potentially help a number of recipients to have a better quality and quantity of life. However, apart from the fact that it is not permitted, such a procedure might have very negative consequences on wider donation rates, as the perception could be that life may be ended specifically to provide organs-a concern that has been expressed in general by some who are reluctant to agree to deceased donation. The principle that individuals are entitled to decide how and when they will die has been established in some countries (Switzerland), but some may struggle with the idea that doctors should participate in organ donation which might either precipitate death or be part of the final interventions.

FIGURE 4
www.frontiersin.org

FIGURE 4. Examples of living donor candidates in the context of euthanasia.

Conclusion

Decision making in the case of living donation remains difficult. There is a lack of detailed objective data regarding the risks in donors with co-morbidities, and the impact on the recipient of not proceeding. There are a number of potentially competing interests, including donor autonomy, the effect on the clinical team and wider societal effects on donation rates. One solution would be to introduce oversight removed from the clinical centre, or to designate some centres as those for “high risk” donors. Consideration of the understanding of risk by the donor may also help guide decisions. This manuscript provides an overview of the relevant issues for a clinical audience, and does not attempt a detailed ethical analysis, which is available in the bioethical literature; we have suggested further reading in Figure 2.

Author Contributions

NM wrote the manuscript. AL and FD coordinated the group and supervised. All other authors contributed to the discussions and writing of the manuscript.

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

We acknowledge the support of the European Society of Transplantation for ELPAT. The ELPAT working group on Living Organ Donation greatly acknowledge Maria Valentin for her contribution to the manuscript during the time she has been involved in the writing process.

Abbreviations

ELPAT, ethical legal and psychological aspects of transplantation; MDM, multidisciplinary meeting; ESRD, end stage renal disease; LDN, living donor nephrectomy.

References

1. Hadjianastassiou, VG, Johnson, RJ, Rudge, CJ, and Mamode, N. 2509 Living Donor Nephrectomies, Morbidity and Mortality, Including the UK Introduction of Laparoscopic Donor Surgery. Am J Transpl (2007) 7(11):2532–7. doi:10.1111/j.1600-6143.2007.01975.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

2. Kortram, K, Ijzermans, JNM, and Dor, FJMF. Perioperative Events and Complications in Minimally Invasive Live Donor Nephrectomy. Transplantation (2016) 100(11):2264–75. doi:10.1097/tp.0000000000001327

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

3. Maple, NH, Hadjianastassiou, V, Jones, R, and Mamode, N. Understanding Risk in Living Donor Nephrectomy. J Med Ethics (2010) 36(3):142–7. doi:10.1136/jme.2009.031740

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

4. Jones, A. Principlism in Medicine - a Philosopher's View. Medicine (2020) 48(10):637–9. doi:10.1016/j.mpmed.2020.07.004

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

5. Beauchamp, TL, and Childress, JF. Principles of Biomedical Ethics. 8th ed. Oxford University Press (2019).

Google Scholar

6. Gillon, R. Ethics Needs Principles-Ffour Can Encompass the Rest-Aand Respect for Autonomy Should Be "first Among Equals". J Med Ethics (2003) 29(5):307–12. doi:10.1136/jme.29.5.307

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

7. Maple, H, Draper, H, Gogalniceanu, P, Burnapp, L, Chilcot, J, and Mamode, N. Donating a Kidney to a Stranger. Ann Surg (2020) 272(1):45–7. doi:10.1097/sla.0000000000003855

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

8. Kisch, AM, Forsberg, A, Fridh, I, Almgren, M, Lundmark, M, Lovén, C, et al. The Meaning of Being a Living Kidney, Liver, or Stem Cell Donor-A Meta-Ethnography. Transplantation (2018) 102(5):744–56. doi:10.1097/tp.0000000000002073

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

9. Draper, H, and Moorlock, G. 8. Unspecified Living Organ Donation. In: SL Hansen, and S Schicktanz, editors. Ethical Challenges of Organ Transplantation: Current Debates and International Perspectives. Bielefeld: Transcript Verlag (2021). p. 151–66. doi:10.1515/9783839446430-010

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

10. Thiessen, C, Gordon, EJ, Reese, PP, and Kulkarni, S. Development of a Donor-Centered Approach to Risk Assessment: Rebalancing Nonmaleficence and Autonomy. Am J Transpl (2015) 15(9):2314–23. doi:10.1111/ajt.13272

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

11. Grill, K. The Normative Core of Paternalism. Res Publica (2007) 13(4):441–58. doi:10.1007/s11158-007-9036-9

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

12. Childress, JF. Public Bioethics: Principles and Problems. USA: Oxford University Press (2020).

Google Scholar

13. Hanna, J. Hard and Soft Paternalism. In: The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Paternalism. Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge (2018). p. 24–34.

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

14. Thys, K, Van Assche, K, Nobile, H, Siebelink, M, Aujoulat, I, Schotsmans, P, et al. Could Minors Be Living Kidney Donors? A Systematic Review of Guidelines, Position Papers and Reports. Transpl Int (2013) 26(10):949–60. doi:10.1111/tri.12097

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

15. Van Assche, K, Genicot, G, and Sterckx, S. Living Organ Procurement from the Mentally Incompetent: The Need for More Appropriate Guidelines. Bioethics (2014) 28(3):101–9. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8519.2012.01982.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

16. Dew, MA, Butt, Z, Humar, A, and DiMartini, AF. Long-Term Medical and Psychosocial Outcomes in Living Liver Donors. Am J Transpl (2017) 17(4):880–92. doi:10.1111/ajt.14111

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

17. Allen, MB, Abt, PL, and Reese, PP. What Are the Harms of Refusing to Allow Living Kidney Donation? an Expanded View of Risks and Benefits. Am J Transplant (2014) 14(3):531–7. doi:10.1111/ajt.12599

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

18. Mandelbrot, DA, Reese, PP, Garg, N, Thomas, CP, Rodrigue, JR, Schinstock, C, et al. KDOQI US Commentary on the 2017 KDIGO Clinical Practice Guideline on the Evaluation and Care of Living Kidney Donors. Am J Kidney Dis (2020) 75(3):299–316. doi:10.1053/j.ajkd.2019.10.005

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

19. Garg, N, Lentine, KL, Inker, LA, Garg, AX, Rodrigue, JR, Segev, DL, et al. Metabolic, Cardiovascular, and Substance Use Evaluation of Living Kidney Donor Candidates: US Practices in 2017. Am J Transpl (2020) 20(12):3390–400. doi:10.1111/ajt.15964

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

20. Grams, ME, Sang, Y, Levey, AS, Matsushita, K, Ballew, S, Chang, AR, et al. Kidney-Failure Risk Projection for the Living Kidney-Donor Candidate. N Engl J Med (2016) 374(5):411–21. doi:10.1056/nejmoa1510491

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

21. Fleisher, LA, Beckman, JA, Brown, KA, Calkins, H, Chaikof, EL, Fleischmann, KE, et al. ACC/AHA 2007 Guidelines on Perioperative Cardiovascular Evaluation and Care for Noncardiac Surgery: Executive Summary. Circulation (20072007) 116(17):1971–96. doi:10.1161/circulationaha.107.185700

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

22. Woo, SH, Marhefka, GD, Cowan, SW, and Ackermann, LJ. Development and Validation of a Prediction Model for Stroke, Cardiac, and Mortality Risk after Non-cardiac Surgery. Am Heart Assoc (2021) 10(4):e018013. doi:10.1161/jaha.120.018013

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

23. Blumenthal-Barby, JS. Biases and Heuristics in Decision Making and Their Impact on Autonomy. Am J Bioeth (2016) 16(5):5–15. doi:10.1080/15265161.2016.1159750

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

24. Heilman, RL, Green, EP, Reddy, KS, Moss, A, and Kaplan, B. Potential Impact of Risk and Loss Aversion on the Process of Accepting Kidneys for Transplantation. Transplantation (2017) 101(7):1514–7. doi:10.1097/tp.0000000000001715

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

25. Lafranca, JA, Spoon, EQW, van de Wetering, J, Ijzermans, JNM, and Dor, FJMF. Attitudes Among Transplant Professionals Regarding Shifting Paradigms in Eligibility Criteria for Live Kidney Donation. Plos One (2120) 12:e0181846. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0181846

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

26. Rakké, YS, Zuidema, WC, Hilhorst, MT, Erdman, RA, Massey, EK, Betjes, MG, et al. Seriously Ill Patients as Living Unspecified Kidney Donors: Rationale and Justification. Transplantation (2015) 99(1):232–5. doi:10.1097/TP.0000000000000281

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

27.Child Killer's Wish to Donate Heart Before Execution Denied. Prison Officials Denied Ronald Phillips' Request Due to Late Notice (2013). Available at: https://abcnews.go.com/US/ohio-death-row-inmate-ronald-phillips-donate-organs/story?id=20863233 (Accessed February 02, 2022).

Google Scholar

28. Wilkinson, D, and Savulescu, J. Should We Allow Organ Donation Euthanasia? Alternatives for Maximizing the Number and Quality of Organs for Transplantation. Bioethics (2012) 26(1):32–48. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8519.2010.01811.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: risk, kidney, transplantation, living donation, autonomy 2

Citation: Mamode N, Van Assche K, Burnapp L, Courtney A, van Dellen D, Houthoff M, Maple H, Moorlock G, Dor FJMF and Lennerling A (2022) Donor Autonomy and Self-Sacrifice in Living Organ Donation: An Ethical Legal and Psychological Aspects of Transplantation (ELPAT) View. Transpl Int 35:10131. doi: 10.3389/ti.2022.10131

Received: 21 October 2021; Accepted: 02 February 2022;
Published: 21 March 2022.

Copyright © 2022 Mamode, Van Assche, Burnapp, Courtney, van Dellen, Houthoff, Maple, Moorlock, Dor and Lennerling. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Nizam Mamode, mamode450@btinternet.com

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.